RE: Toggling nature's auto-erase

From: joedees@bellsouth.net
Date: Fri Mar 16 2001 - 22:35:02 GMT

  • Next message: joedees@bellsouth.net: "RE: Toggling nature's auto-erase"

    Received: by alpheratz.cpm.aca.mmu.ac.uk id WAA25713 (8.6.9/5.3[ref pg@gmsl.co.uk] for cpm.aca.mmu.ac.uk from fmb-majordomo@mmu.ac.uk); Fri, 16 Mar 2001 22:32:23 GMT
    From: <joedees@bellsouth.net>
    To: memetics@mmu.ac.uk
    Date: Fri, 16 Mar 2001 16:35:02 -0600
    Content-type: text/plain; charset=US-ASCII
    Content-transfer-encoding: 7BIT
    Subject: RE: Toggling nature's auto-erase
    Message-ID: <3AB240B6.17614.504F0B@localhost>
    In-reply-to: <JJEIIFOCALCJKOFDFAHBMECHCHAA.richard@brodietech.com>
    References: <3AB0DAED.33.6217BF@localhost>
    X-mailer: Pegasus Mail for Win32 (v3.12c)
    Sender: fmb-majordomo@mmu.ac.uk
    Precedence: bulk
    Reply-To: memetics@mmu.ac.uk
    

    On 15 Mar 2001, at 20:16, Richard Brodie wrote:

    > Joe Dees wrote:
    >
    > <<Brodie's Level 3 begins there, then goes on to state that one
    > should choose in what to believe, regardless of its truth, based
    > upon its usefulness to oneself, and continue to believe it only so
    > long as it is useful. I have not achieved that ability to believe my
    > own lies when I know that what I'm telling to myself are pragmatically
    > chosen lies, nor do I wish to achieve such a hypocritical condition.
    > Once one begins lying to oneself, and begins to accept that lying to
    > oneself for selfish social, political or economic reasons is OK, it
    > becomes shamefully (or shamelessly) easy to lie to others, a
    > Nietszchean observation concerning a basic principle underlying the
    > proliferation of ridiculously irrational beliefs and belief systems,
    > literal christianity chief among them.>>
    >
    > There are plenty of beliefs that are neither "truth" nor "lie." Many
    > of these can be broadly categorized as attitudes. Others are labels or
    > distinctions. Choosing not to believe a truth is rarely useful, but
    > choosing among attitudes and labels is immensely so.
    >
    People may take attitudes towards assertions, but attitudes are
    not root assertions themselves, but reference such assertions;
    there is a primorial 'aboutness' about attitudes - they are about
    assertions other than themselves.
    May one reasonably choose, within limits, the perspective one
    takes regarding the demonstrably true or the demonstrably false?
    Iff that perspective is denial, it will certainly fail. When the
    Alabama Congress passed a law that in the state pi was to equal
    three, not 3.14159.., because of a bible passage, state buildings
    built according to the legally ratified falsity would not stand, and the
    absurdity was repealed. Remembering, following Popper, that it is
    impossible to prove a universal empirical assertion absolutely true
    (for to do so would foreclose a future in which contrafactual
    evidence might appear) but possible to prove such an assertion
    absolutely false (by means of contrefactual evidence or internal/self-
    contradiction), what perspective does one choose with reference to
    the demonstrably (provisionally) true or (absolutely) false? Is it
    useful to say that one does not like a particular truth one
    nevertheless acknowledges, or that one likes a particular lie one
    knows to be untrue, and how do such choices generalize to one's
    perspective upon truth and lies generally, and how does that effect
    one's personal and/or intellectual integrity? If an assertion is not
    testable, then it may or may not be believed in, but one must be
    honest enough with oneself and others to acknowledge that one is
    in a state of believing, not a state of knowing. Of course, internally,
    that is, subjectively, believing-in and knowing may feel the same,
    but externally, the distinction is easily made, by reference to the
    presence or absence of evidence for the contention, and whether
    the contention is even in principle testable (ref. ON MEANING by
    Algirdas Julien Greimas, ch. 10 (pp. 165-179): "Knowing and
    Believing: A Single Cognitive Universe"). It is also impossible to
    believe in (or not believe in) a meaningless assertion; one may
    simply ascertain whether or not an assertion is meaningless by
    subjecting it to syntactic and semantic analysis. It is impossible,
    for example, to believe that "colorless green ideas sleep furiously"
    (an example of ac semantically meaningless yet syntactically
    unobjectionable statement from INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC by
    Irving Copi).

    To close, there are four categories:
    1) (provisionally) true
    2) false
    3) untestable yet meaningful (metaphysical, ethical, aesthetic and
    religious assertions)
    4) meaningless

    Only in category #3 can Richard's caveat apply.

    >
    > ===============================================================
    > This was distributed via the memetics list associated with the
    > Journal of Memetics - Evolutionary Models of Information Transmission
    > For information about the journal and the list (e.g. unsubscribing)
    > see: http://www.cpm.mmu.ac.uk/jom-emit
    >
    >

    ===============================================================
    This was distributed via the memetics list associated with the
    Journal of Memetics - Evolutionary Models of Information Transmission
    For information about the journal and the list (e.g. unsubscribing)
    see: http://www.cpm.mmu.ac.uk/jom-emit



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2b29 : Fri Mar 16 2001 - 22:35:35 GMT