Kilroy Was Here

From: Joe E. Dees (joedees@bellsouth.net)
Date: Thu Mar 09 2000 - 02:44:41 GMT

  • Next message: Robert G. Grimes: "Re: Martin Gardner's two cents"

    Received: by alpheratz.cpm.aca.mmu.ac.uk id CAA02675 (8.6.9/5.3[ref pg@gmsl.co.uk] for cpm.aca.mmu.ac.uk from fmb-majordomo@mmu.ac.uk); Thu, 9 Mar 2000 02:42:36 GMT
    Message-Id: <200003090240.VAA04437@mail4.lig.bellsouth.net>
    From: "Joe E. Dees" <joedees@bellsouth.net>
    To: memetics@mmu.ac.uk
    Date: Wed, 8 Mar 2000 20:44:41 -0600
    Content-type: text/plain; charset=US-ASCII
    Content-transfer-encoding: 7BIT
    Subject: Kilroy Was Here
    X-mailer: Pegasus Mail for Win32 (v3.12b)
    Sender: fmb-majordomo@mmu.ac.uk
    Precedence: bulk
    Reply-To: memetics@mmu.ac.uk
    

            The word "meme" was introduced in an offhand way by Oxford
    University biologist Richard Dawkins at the end of his book "The
    Selfish Gene." Reviewers of Dawkins' book liked to quote Samuel
    Butler's remark that a chicken is an egg's way of making another
    egg. Dawkins' theme was similar. An organism is a gene's way of
    making other genes. The genes are "selfish in the sense that they
    care not a fig about the welfare of the organisms that preserve and
    keep them going."
            A meme (it rhymes with "dream") is short for mimetics, a word
    denoting mimicry. Dawkins wanted to identify a self-replicating unit
    of culture that would play a role in cultural evolution similar in some
    ways to the role played by self-replicating genes in the evolution of
    bodies. He chose the word "meme" because it had one syllable,
    like gene, and because it sounded like gene.
            A meme is anything humans do or say that is not genetically
    determined and is passed from person to person by imitation or
    copying, such as the wish to "have a nice day." The term has
    already entered the Oxford English Dictionary, in which it is defined
    as "an element of a culture that may be considered to be passed
    on by nongenetic means, esp. imitation." Memes are invisible self-
    replicators that live in human brains the way genes live in cells.
    They become tangible when they jump from one brain to another.
    Relativity theory, for example, slumbered in Einstein's brain as a
    meme before it went public in a technical paper.
            After memes were tossed into the English language by
    Dawkins, memetics quickly caught fire, especially on the Internet,
    where it has a cult-like following. Daniel Dennett, Tufts University's
    energetic and wide-ranging philosopher, has become the top
    fugleman of memetics. He vigorously defends the meme concept at
    length in "Consciousness Explained" and at even greater length in
    "Darwin's Dangerous Idea." But, as I will argue here, a meme is so
    broadly defined by its proponents as to be a useless concept,
    creating more confusion than light, and I predict that the concept
    will soon be forgotten as a curious linguistic quirk of little value.
            Every idea or form of behavior that you learned from someone
    else, not on your own, is a meme. The list is endless: gestures,
    tunes, catch phrases like "Kilroy was here," fashions in clothes
    such as the current droopy trousers worn by young boys, ways to
    make anything (pots, chairs, cars, planes, skyscrapers), marriage
    customs, diet fads, art, novels, poems, plays, operas, tools,
    games, inventions, ideas in science, philosophy and religion--all
    are memes. What sociologists call mores and folkways are
    memes. From a "meme's-eye view"--a favorite phrase of
    memeticists--all your beliefs about anything are clusters of memes.
    If you are a skeptic, your skepticism is made of memes. Was
    Jesus the son of God? If you think yes, that's a meme. If you think
    no, that's also a meme.
            There are three ways in which memes leap from person to
    person. They jump vertically from parents to offspring. They jump
    horizontally from person to person in ways resembling the spread
    of a virus. Third, memes can move obliquely from someone to a
    near relative or friend. All words are memes. Spoken and written
    languages are clusters of memes.
            Along with Dennett, two authors in 1996 also promoted the
    meme craze: Richard Brodie in "Viruses of the Mind: The New
    Science of the Meme" and Aaron Lynch in "Thought Contagion:
    How Belief Spreads Through Society." Last year came a third
    spirited defense of memetics, "The Meme Machine" by Susan J.
    Blackmore, a psychologist at the University of the West of England
    in Bristol. Born in London in 1951, she is best known today among
    parapsychologists and skeptics for her disenchantment with
    psychic research. Blackmore goes far beyond her predecessors in
    her enthusiasm for memetics. In his foreword to "The Meme
    Machine" Dawkins recognizes that Blackmore's vision of the future
    of memetics far exceeds his own. She has "greater courage and
    intellectual chutzpah," he writes, "than I have ever aspired to. . . ."
    Indeed, Blackmore speaks of her book as actually laying the
    foundation for a new science.
                                                 * * *
            Blackmore believes that certain big questions can be answered
    fully only by invoking memes; for example, why do we have such
    large brains? The conventional answer is that complex thinking has
    enormous survival value in the ability of a species to control its
    environment and keep itself from extinction. Blackmore puts it
    differently. Our brains are meme machines that have evolved to
    store and transmit memes. We are back to a version of Butler's
    topsy-turvy aphorism. Instead of brains creating memes, such as
    Huckleberry Finn and quantum mechanics, it is the other way
    around. "The enormous human brain," she writes, "has been
    created by the memes."
            Many pages of "The Meme Machine" concern ways in which
    memes influence sexual behavior. All cultures have memes about
    what makes a person sexually attractive. Two such popular memes
    are that women should marry men taller and older than themselves.
    Such memes obviously influence mating choices, but Blackmore
    argues that we should override such trivial rules and mate with
    those who are the most skillful in "copying, using, and spreading
    memes."
            More drastic than her view of gender relations, Blackmore's
    thesis attacks Western civilization's understanding of the self. In
    the book's final chapter, Blackmore follows Dennett in seeing
    consciousness and free will (two names for essentially the same
    thing) as illusions. They are "explained" by simply denying that
    they are real. For Blackmore and Dennett, the notion of a "self"
    living inside our brain--an entity that makes decisions--is what
    Blackmore calls an "insidious and pervasive" notion created by the
    millions of memes that shuffle about inside our skull. There is, to
    put it bluntly, no such thing as a self:
            "If I genuinely believe that there is no 'I' inside, with free will and
    conscious deliberate choice, then how do I decide what to do? The
    answer is to have faith in the memetic view; to accept that the
    selection of genes and memes will determine the action and there
    is no need for an extra 'me' to get involved. To live honestly, I must
    just get out of the way and allow decisions to make themselves.
            "On this view, all human actions, whether conscious or not,
    become complex interactions between memes, genes and all their
    products, in complicated environments. The self is not the initiator
    of actions, it does not 'have' consciousness and it does not 'do' the
    deliberating. There is no truth in the idea of an inner self inside my
    body that controls the body and is conscious. Because this is
    false, so is the idea of my conscious self having free will."
            And here is how Blackmore describes the illusions of the self in
    "The Meme Machine's" final paragraph:
            "Memetics thus brings us to a new vision of how we might live
    our lives. We can carry on our lives as most people do, under the
    illusion that there is a persistent conscious self inside who is in
    charge, who is responsible for my actions and who makes me me.
    Or we can live as human beings, body, brain, and memes, living
    out our lives as a complex interplay of replicators and environment,
    in the knowledge that that is all there is. Then we are no longer
    victims of the selfish selfplex. In this sense we can be truly free--not
    because we can rebel against the tyranny of the selfish replicators
    but because we know that there is no one to rebel."
            Observe how this denial of a self meshes with the statement
    Butler made in jest. Instead of humans thinking about the world
    and their lives, exchanging information, inventing things, interacting
    with one another, experiencing pleasures and pains, the memetic
    language reverses everything. It's like bending over and looking at
    the world between your legs. You see the same things as before
    but from a different perspective. What is really going on is that
    billions of selfish memes are manipulating us. They have taken over
    our brains. They shape all our thoughts and actions. The memes
    are not our creations. We are theirs. We are just a meme's way of
    making other memes.
            Because Blackmore shares Dennett's belief that all our
    decisions are determined by genes and memes--what we are wired
    to do by heredity and experience--she joins the ranks of thinkers
    known as determinists. One wonders what she would make of
    such famous arguments for free will as those found in William
    James' essay "The Dilemma of Determinism" or the attacks on
    determinists by later philosophers.
            Note the word "selfplex" in the last paragraph of Blackmore's
    book. It is her term for the cluster of genes and memes that gives
    rise to the illusion of a self. This brings us to the most serious
    objection that critics have hurled at memeticists: The notion of a
    meme is too fuzzy, too ill-defined.
            A meme is supposed to be an element of imitation that can
    serve as a significant cultural unit. There have been a few earlier
    efforts to define such units. Blackmore cites two: "corpuscles of
    culture," proposed by anthropologist F.T. Cloak in 1975, and
    "culturgens," an equally ugly term suggested by physicist Charles
    Lumsden and biologist Edward O. Wilson in 1981. Neither has
    caught on. The question arises: Given that there are cultural
    elements called memes, how do we distinguish a single meme,
    such as the "V for victory" gesture, from a vast bundle of memes,
    such as those that constitute a religion?
            To answer this question, memeticists have invented the word
    "memeplex" to denote a cluster of memes. Hilarious debates have
    raged over how to draw lines separating memes from memeplexes.
    For example, the first four notes of Beethoven's Fifth Symphony (da-
    da-da-dum), as Blackmore records them, clearly are a meme
    because millions of people can hum those four notes without being
    able to hum the entire symphony. The symphony is, of course,
    also a meme, but best described as a memeplex because it
    consists of smaller memes.
            The question of where to mark the boundaries along meme
    spectrums is not easy. "Laugh and the world laughs with you;
    weep and you weep alone." This clearly is a meme because so
    many people can repeat it without knowing they are reciting the
    opening lines of "Solitude," a poem by Ella Wheeler Wilcox. All
    poems and novels are memeplexes. They often contain memorable
    lines that jump from person to person because they are so easily
    remembered. "Call me Ishmael," the first line of "Moby Dick," is a
    meme. The first chapter of the novel is a memeplex, and the entire
    novel is a larger memeplex.
            All of science is a memeplex, but it is hopeless to decide when
    a scientific assertion becomes small enough to be called an
    individual meme. Is the fact of evolution a meme or a memeplex?
    Roman Catholicism is a monstrous memeplex. What aspects of it
    deserve to be called memes? The doctrine of the Immaculate
    Conception? Or is this a memeplex made up of such memes as
    original sin and the Virgin Birth? Should an entire mass be called a
    meme or a memeplex? The gesture of crossing the heart is surely
    a meme, but we encounter great difficulty sorting out the memes
    that make up a doctrine as complicated as, say, the Atonement.
            The point is that the notion of a meme is much too broad to be
    useful in explaining human thinking and behavior. A meme is little
    more than a peculiar terminology for saying the obvious. Who can
    deny that cultures change in ways independent of genetics, ways
    involving information that is spread throughout society mainly by
    spoken and written words?
            As Blackmore makes clear, memes have a physical basis of
    some sort inside brains, where they are stored in one's memory in
    ways nobody understands. This is important in helping us
    understand how memes and genes differ. Genes have become
    visible. They are spots along the DNA double helix that have been
    isolated and observed. They are as real as atoms. How memes live
    in brains is a mystery.
            When memes jump from brain to brain, they often are
    transported by what memeticists call meme vehicles. Obvious
    examples of such carriers are newspapers, periodicals, books and
    recordings. Libraries, museums and art galleries are huge vehicles
    for storing and passing along memes. "A scholar," writes Dennett,
    paraphrasing Butler, "is just a library's way of making another
    library."
            For Dennett and Blackmore, memes offer profound new
    insights into human nature and even lead to theories which may
    soon be testable. They see memetics as a science in its infancy.
    To critics, who at the moment far outnumber true believers,
    memetics is no more than a cumbersome terminology for saying
    what everybody knows and that can be more usefully said in the
    dull terminology of information transfer.
            Stephen Jay Gould, in a 1996 debate with Blackmore, called
    memes "meaningless metaphors." Blackmore cites a letter in the
    New Scientist in which British philosopher Mary Midgley calls
    memes "mythical entities" that are a "useless and essentially
    superstitious notion." H. Allen Ore, a University of Rochester
    geneticist, was quoted in Time as dismissing memetics as "an
    utterly silly idea. It's just a cocktail party science."
            Let's try a linguistic thought experiment. In all human cultures,
    even in chimp society, objects not connected to the body are
    shifted from place to place. Call every such move a "tran," short for
    translocate or transfer. Moving our shoes when we walk, run or
    dance is not trans because the objects are attached to our body.
    Nor are the movements of things in cars, trains, ships, planes and
    elevators examples of trans because the propelling forces are
    independent of us even though we may direct such movements.
            Examples of genuine trans abound. The motions of pitched and
    batted baseballs are obvious trans, as are the movements of
    objects in dozens of other sports: football, basketball, bowling,
    tennis, golf, hockey, pool and so on. When a chess player pushes
    a pawn, it's a tran. Dealing playing cards is a tran. Raking leaves
    and moving vacuum cleaners and using dust busters are trans.
    Serving food and washing dishes are trans. Hammering a nail and
    sawing wood are trans. Eating is a tran because food is moved from
    plate to mouth, though swallowing it is not because the food
    becomes joined to the body. Punching typewriter and computer
    keys are trans. Moving piano keys, trumpet valves and drumsticks
    are trans. Digging ditches and cutting down trees are trans. Serving
    beer is a tran. There are tens of thousands of other examples.
            A vexing question arises: How should we distinguish trans from
    transplexes? The flight of a pitched baseball is a tran, but if the ball
    is hit, caught and tossed to first base, is that familiar sequence a
    tran or a transplex? Shall we call an entire inning a tran or a
    transplex? Should transplex be reserved for a complete game, with
    its hundreds of trans?
            What is gained by introducing the concept of a tran? Nothing.
    Trans are no more than a bizarre terminology for saying what is
    better said in ordinary language. We don't need a new science of
    tranetics to tell us that in every culture, persons move things.
            Are memes here to stay or will they prove to be as irrelevant as
    trans? Will memetics turn out to be a new science or a harmless
    humbug destined to evaporate like Kurt Lewin's topological
    psychology, which befuddled Gestalt psychologists in the 1930s,
    or catastrophe theory, which two decades ago agitated a small
    group of overzealous mathematicians? Is memetics a misguided
    attempt on the part of behavioral scientists to imitate genetics with
    its gene units and physics with its elementary particles? In a few
    years we may know.

    ===============================================================
    This was distributed via the memetics list associated with the
    Journal of Memetics - Evolutionary Models of Information Transmission
    For information about the journal and the list (e.g. unsubscribing)
    see: http://www.cpm.mmu.ac.uk/jom-emit



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2b29 : Thu Mar 09 2000 - 02:42:43 GMT