Logo  Castro L. and Toro, M. A. (2002). Cultural Transmission and the Capacity to Approve or Disapprove of Offspring’s Behaviour.
Journal of Memetics - Evolutionary Models of Information Transmission, 6.
http://cfpm.org/jom-emit/2002/vol6/castro_l&toro_ma.html

Cultural Transmission and the Capacity to Approve or Disapprove of Offspring’s Behaviour

Laureano Castro and Miguel A. Toro
Departamento de Mejora Genética Animal, SGIT-INIA,
Carretera de La Coruña km. 7, 28040 Madrid, Spain.
lcastro@madrid.uned.es toro@inia.es
Abstract
1 - Introduction
2. The model
2.1 Trial and error learning
2.2 Imitation
2.3 To approve or disapprove of offspring’s behaviour
2.4 Genetic model
3. Results
3.1 Without selection
3.2 With selection, but without cost for assessor (c = 0)
3.3 With selection and with cost for assessor (c > 0)
4. Discussion
4.1 Imitator versus only-learner: is imitation adaptive?
4.2 Only-assessor versus only-learner: is transmission of evaluations adaptive?
4.3 Assessor: are both imitation and transmission of evaluations together adaptive?
4.4 Conclusion
5. Appendix
References




 

Abstract.

We suggest that human cultural learning was made possible by the simultaneous appearance, in one of our hominid ancestors, of two capacities: the capacity to imitate others’ behaviour and the capacity to approve or disapprove of others’ behaviour. With the help of a mathematical model, we have studied the conditions that allow the evolution of both capacities. We consider four different genotypes: "the only-learner" that learns by trial and error, "the imitator" that learns by trial and error and imitation, "the only-assessor" that learns by trial and error but that can also approve or disapprove of offspring's behaviour and, finally, "the assessor", who behaves like the imitator but, he can approve or disapprove of offspring's behaviour. The assessor genotype is the best genotype and the only-learner genotype is the worst when the learned behaviour that would be culturally transmitted is adaptive. If this behaviour is maladaptive, the genotype only-assessor is the best genotype and the genotype assessor can be the worst genotype. Notwithstanding, in this situation, the assessor can also be better than the imitator and even better than the only-learner. The success of assessor is due to his capacity to increase the phenotypic correlation between parents and offspring, and thus speeding the rate at which natural selection, if present, will increase or decrease the frequency of learned behaviours.
Keywords: Conceptual categorisation; assessor; imitation; teaching; cultural evolution.



Introduction


In species having a certain trial and error learning capacity the development of a system of cultural transmission can turn out to be adaptive because individuals do not need to reinvent behaviour. Boyd & Richerson (1985) propose that cultural transmission provides a short-cut in time and costs as compared to individual learning. However, culture has only reached an important level of development in Homo sapiens. In non-human animals forms of cultural transmission are absent or limited to a narrow range of behaviours, as is the case of song learning in song birds, or rudimentary, as seems to be the case in apes (Whiten & Ham, 1992; Heyes & Galef, 1996). Besides, in recent years, monkeys’ imitative ability has been questioned (Galef, 1988; Visalberghi & Fragaszy, 1990; Tomasello, 1996). At the heart of the controversy lies an interesting distinction between "true imitation", in which one animal copies the behaviour pattern of a performer it has observed, and "stimulus enhancement", in which a performer’s action merely focuses an observer’s attention on critical environmental features, increasing the speed with which the observer subsequently learns a similar behaviour pattern through its own efforts. This can have evolutionary importance, because cumulative culture change is possible when there is imitation but not when there is stimulus enhancement (Boyd & Richerson, 1995). Several reviews suggest that all known cases of animal social traditions can be explained as the result of stimulus enhancement (Tomasello, 1990; Galef, 1992; Tomasello, 1996), although the question still remains open (Whiten, 1998; Byrne & Russon, 1998; Custance et al., 1999; Whiten et al., 1999).

In the literature on cultural transmission, trial and error learning and imitation are usually two alternative kinds of learning device (see Aoki, 2001, for a review). Cultural organisms can have in their brains a switching mechanism by which the organism can use either one or the other under different circumstances. In these models, each organism can learn individually or socially, but it cannot use both options at once. When individuals use trial and error learning, they learn the appropriate behaviour but they suffer learning costs. When they use imitation, individuals adopt permanently the behaviour of the individual that they use as a model and, therefore, avoid the costs of individual learning, but suffering a cost if they imitate an inappropriate model. Stable equilibrium might be achieved through a mixed strategy involving either polymorphism between imitative and creative individuals, or more realistically, individuals displaying both modes of behaviour (Boyd & Richerson, 1985; Feldman et. al., 1996; Henrich & Boyd, 1998).

In the model we propose here the relationship between trial and error learning and imitation is considered in a different manner. The adoption of a behaviour is defined as a process with three steps: the first, to discover and to learn the behaviour, the second, to evaluate behaviour as good or bad, and the third, to reject or to incorporate it into the behavioural repertory. Cultural organisms can to discover and learn a behaviour -the first step- both through trial and error learning or imitation. Thus, imitation increases the probability of discovering and learning a behaviour pattern from parents, but afterwards the individuals have to evaluate the learned behaviour through their evaluative brain structures and they can adopt or reject the behaviour that has been imitated. The same process occurs when cultural individuals discover by trial and error behaviours that they have not observed in other individuals. Therefore, imitation is an alternative process to trial and error learning with respect to discover a behaviour but not with respect to its final rejection or adoptation. We think that this model describes better the interaction between imitation and trial and error learning in the chimpanzées and it must be the starting point to study the evolution of cultural transmission in the hominids.

Moreover, we consider that our hominid ancestors have developed the conceptual capacity to categorise behaviour. This capacity is defined as the ability to categorise one's own and others' behaviour through a non verbal conceptual value code -positive/negative, good/bad- which works with the same evaluative brain structures that control trial and error learning (Castro, 1992; Castro & Toro, 1995; Castro & Toro, 1998). This represents the transformation of an automatic mechanism of categorizing behaviour in a mechanism of conceptual categorization. We have suggested that hominids with this ability to categorise -that we call hominid assessor- could approve or disapprove of other's behaviour. In this paper, we analyse how this ability to approve or disapprove of behaviour can be adaptive if it occurs between parents and offspring because parents can help the offspring to accept the good behaviour and to reject the bad one. Ethnographic records show teaching, defined as an instructed learning of behaviours, abilities or skills, are rare among human foragers and in most simple human societies (Rogoff, 1990; Tomasello et al., 1993; Tomasello, 1999). However, we think that the transmission from parents to offspring of information on the evaluation of the learned behaviour is a process of cultural transmission that must be denominated teaching and we suggest that teaching, defined in this way, is present in all human societies. That is, teaching is characteristic of our species.

Our model is a model of gene-culture evolution but we think like Kendal and Laland (2000) that these kind of models could be very useful in memetics. More specifically our aim is to emphasise the importance that the ability to approve or disapprove of other’s behaviour has for the meme evolution.



 

2. The Model

The model is based, at least partially, on the models of cultural transmission proposed by Maynard Smith & Warren (1982), Feldman & Cavalli-Sforza (1984) and on our previous model (Castro & Toro, 1995). Our interest is to define a model of cultural transmission that can be applied to our hominid ancestors. We assume that those hominids had a cognitive ability similar to present-day chimpanzees and they lack the language capacity. They acquired most of their learned behaviour by trial and error learning although some of them were also able to learn by imitation. Finally, we assume that some individuals had also developed the capacity to categorise behaviour -approving or disapproving of offspring’s behaviour.
 

2.1 Trial and error learning


The adoption of a behaviour through trial and error learning can be divided into three stages. The first is to discover and to experiment with the behaviour. The second is to evaluate the behaviour, and the third, to accept or to reject it. We will call "status" the set of behaviours that an individual discovers and evaluates during his ontogeny.

The model assumes that behaviour can be described as a dichotomy: to do something (1) vs. to do nothing (0). If there is only one behaviour 1 –for example, to eat a particular vegetable (1) vs. not to eat it (0)- the status of an individual can be status 1 or status 0 if he knows or does not know behaviour 1, respectively. The probability of an individual discovering and testing behaviour 1 is h -the probability of this behaviour being part of his status. In this model, behaviour 0 – to do nothing- is always present in the status.

At the end of the ontogenic period, the individual has to decide the behaviours that he finally will incorporate into his behavioural repertory. If the status is 1, b is the probability that he decides to incorporate behaviour 1 instead of rejecting it. The parameters h and b represent the probability of complex processes that depend on many factors. We deliberately exclude the observation of other individuals’ behaviour from those factors that affect parameters h and b .
 

2.2 Imitation


All individuals can discover the behaviour through trial and error learning, but cultural individuals can also discover it through imitation. Imitation is introduced in the model by a parameter a that represents the probability of learning a behaviour by observing it in the parents -vertical cultural transmission. Imitation increases the probability h that an individual learns and tests the active behaviour that his parents exhibit but it does not affect the probability b of accepting or rejecting it. For simplicity, we assume that cultural transmission of behaviour is determined by choosing as a model only one of its parents, the mother. The matrix of transmission between parents and children is given in table 1.
 

 
Probability of a child acquiring status
Mother's behaviour
Status 0
Status 1
Behaviour 0
(1-h)
h
Behaviour 1
(1-h*)
h*
Table 1. Probability of a child acquiring status 0 or 1

where h* = (h + (1 - h) a ) is the probability of an individual learning the behaviour 1 when his mother is 1. In this expression, a represents the intensity of the process of cultural transmission and (1-h)a measures the net effect of this process. At the end of the period of ontogeny, the individual decides the behaviour that he finally will exhibit depending on the same parameter b as in the individual learning case.

The model assumes that only the active behaviour 1 can be observed and, therefore, can be culturally transmitted, but not the absence of a behaviour, 0. Therefore, 1 is a cultural trait but 0 is not. In the discussion we consider the situation where both behaviours, 1 and 0, can be imitated. We also consider what happens when other individuals different from parents are imitated -i.e., oblique and horizontal transmission..
 

2.3 To approve or disapprove of offspring’s behaviour


The model assumes that some individuals that we call assessors have the ability to approve or disapprove of learned behaviour of their offspring whereas non-assessor individuals do not have this ability. The parameter d measures the intensity of approval or reproof made by the assessor parent (0 £ d £ 1). This parameter d increases or decreases the probability b of offspring accepting a behaviour depending on whether it has been approved or disapproved of by the parents. The behaviour 1 will be approved if the parental model has adopted this behaviour and it will be disapproved of only if the parental model knows this behaviour -it is present in its status- but it has rejected it. For simplicity, only one of the parents, the mother, approves or disapproves of a child's behaviour. If the status is 1, b* is the probability that assessor prefers to incorporate behaviour 1 instead of rejecting it. b* depends on the evaluation of the behaviour:

If the evaluation is positive b* will be

    b* =+ (1 - b )d

If the evaluation is negative b* will be

    b-* = b- bd
 

2.4 Genetic model


The process of transmission is assumed to be controlled by a sexual haploid genetic system with two loci, one for imitation and the other for categorisation, with two alleles per locus (I/i) and (A/a), respectively. Therefore, four genotypes are distinguished:

- ia: "non-imitator and non-assessor" or "only-learner" (without ability either to imitate or to transmit evaluations):a = d = 0

- iA: "only-assessor" (with ability to transmit evaluations but without ability to imitate):

    a  = 0 and 0 < d < 1

- Ia: "imitator" (with ability to imitate but without ability to transmit evaluations):

    0 < a < 1 and d = 0

- IA: "assessor": (with ability to both imitate and transmit evaluations):

    0 < a < 1 and 0 < d < 1

Each one of these four genotypes can adopt three different phenotypes depending on the status and the behaviour exhibited and therefore there will be 12 distinct phenogenotypes. For example, for only-learner: ia-00 (they don’t do 1 because they don’t know 1), ia-01 (they don’t do 1 because they don’t want), and ia-11 (they do 1), where the superscript represents the status. It is also assumed that the only differences among genotypes are due to the values of a and d .

The use of a haploid genetic system is justified because it provides an approximation to the situation of intermediate dominance in diploid systems, especially near of the state of allelic fixation (Feldman & Cavalli-Sforza, 1984). Mating occurs randomly and from each mating the offspring genotypes are produced with the standard Mendelian probabilities, using the recombination fraction r. Mutation is assumed to be absent. The action of natural selection occurs when the individual has decided his behaviour after the ontogeny period and before mating. The fitness of phenotypes 0 and 1 is 1 and 1+s, respectively, s being the selective value. Each individual is given a certain probability of removal from the population based on s.

The possible costs of learning are not considered in the model, because we assume that these costs are the same across all the different genotypes. Obviously, this can be unrealistic. In fact, imitation allows the offspring to quickly get to know the behaviours that the parents exhibit and, if these behaviours are adaptive, they can profit from them earlier. However, this rapidity can be a disadvantage if the imitated behaviour is maladaptive for the offspring, either because it is harmful in itself or because the offspring is too young to practice the behaviour correctly. Furthermore, the capacity to imitate does not preclude the possibility that the offspring explores and evaluates not only the imitated behaviours but also other new behaviours that the parents do not exhibit and, therefore, the offspring also suffers learning costs. In the other hand, the capacity to approve or disapprove of offspring’s behaviour can facilitate the evaluation of the behaviour, but it can also have a fitness cost c that represents a cost of parental care. We have preferred to ignore the possible differences in the learning costs and to analyse only the existence of fitness cost c for only-assessor and for assessor.



 

3. Results

 

3.1 Without selection


The evolution of phenotypic frequencies in the absence of selection, together with the equilibrium values in genotypically monomorphic populations and in the absence of selection is given in the Appendix. From there, it can be seen that the equilibrium frequency of the phenotype 1 in these populations follows the decreasing order

    IA > Ia > iA = ia

The allele I allows imitation. The imitation decreases the frequency of status 0 and increases the frequency of status 1, and this results in a decrease in the equilibrium frequency of phenotype 0 and an increase in the equilibrium frequency of phenotype 1, the behaviour that can be imitated. The effect of imitation is stronger when the behaviour is more difficult to learn by individual learning -low values of h. In fact, if h = 1 there is no difference between imitator and only-learner. Obviously, the effect of imitation will increase as a , the ability to imitate maternal behaviour 1, increases. For a given value of h, the effect of a is stronger as bincreases.

The allele A allows their carriers, when they act as mothers, to approve or disapprove of the behaviour that their offspring has learned if and only if they know the behaviour, that is, if it is present in the mother status. The A allele increases the phenotypic correlation between mothers 1 (11) and their offspring and between mothers 0 with status 1 (01) and their offspring. This phenotypic correlation will increase as the parameter d -the ability to transmit evaluations- increases. If d = 1, all offspring of mothers 1 that acquire status 1 will be 1 and, on the contrary, all the offspring of mothers 0 with status 1 (01) will be 0. The effect of d is stronger as b decreases.
 

3.2 With selection, but without cost for assessor (c = 0)


With selection, the system is too complex to be solved analytically, although it can be easily iterated in a computer (the software used for simulation is available from the authors upon request). The frequency of the different phenogenotypes when equilibrium is reached has been calculated in different situations for populations composed of the four genotypes with selection either in favour or against the phenotype 1 (figures 1-8). The initial distribution of four genotypes was 25% for each one. The initial distribution of status and phenotypes was 100% 00. The recombination fraction r was 0.5, although using other values does not qualitatively change the results.

With selection there is always a genotype that eliminates the others and goes to fixation. We can analyse the ranking among the four genotypes by looking at the order in which they are eliminated. If the behaviour that can be imitated 1 has positive selective value (figures 1-4), assessor is always the best genotype and only-learner is the worst. The other two genotypes, imitator and only-assessor have an intermediate position. From the frequency at equilibrium without selection of phenotype 1 in each one of the genotypically monomorphic populations we would expect that the relative fitness of genotypes would be Ia > iA, because the genotype imitator Ia produces a greater frequency of individuals 1 than genotype only-assessor iA (figures 1, 3, and 4). However, this is not always the case. The genotype only-assessor iA can be better than genotype imitator Ia if the increase in the frequency of phenotype 1 produced by imitation is small -h big-, the effect due to selection s is great enough, and the effect of the transmission of evaluations is great -b small (figure 2). Thus, only-assessor is advantageous in the probably uncommon situations where the individuals reject behaviours that are adaptive.


Figure 1. Evolution of genotypic frequencies with positive selection for phenotype 1 


Figure 2. Evolution of genotypic frequencies with positive selection for phenotype 1 


Figure 3. Evolution of genotypic frequencies with positive selection for phenotype 1


Figure 4. Evolution of genotypic frequencies with positive selection for phenotype 1 

If behaviour that can be imitated 1 has negative selective value, only-assessor is always the best genotype and eliminates the others (figures 5-8). The reason why only-assessor is superior to only-learner under these circumstances is because only-assessors are able to increase the fitness of their offspring. From the frequencies at equilibrium without selection, the expected ranking of the genotypes should be: iA > ia> Ia > IA (figures 5 and 7). However, the genotype assessor can be better than imitator, iA > ia > IA > Ia (figure 8), if the selection coefficient s against phenotype 1 is great and the effect of imitation increasing the frequency of behaviour 1 is small –h big. And it can even be better than only-learner iA > IA > ia > Ia (figure 6), if the probability b of accepting the maladaptive behaviour 1 is sufficiently small. Thus, assessor is advantageous if the maladaptive behaviour is easy to learn and to reject.


Figure 5. Evolution of genotypic frequencies with negative selection against phenotype 1 


Figure 6. Evolution of genotypic frequencies with negative selection against phenotype 1


Figure 7. Evolution of genotypic frequencies with negative selection against phenotype 1 


Figure 8. Evolution of genotypic frequencies with negative selection against phenotype 1 


3.3 With selection and with cost for assessor (c > 0)


If the approval or disapproval of the behaviour exhibited by the offspring has a cost c, assessor and only-assessor can lose their advantage in some of the previous situations. The cost comes from the time and energy devoted to influence the offspring’s behaviour. Obviously, this will depend on the benefit of evaluation outweighing or not the cost. However, it is important to bear in mind that a given amount of parental investment can be used to control simultaneously several behaviours learned by the offspring. Thus the cost will be attenuated because it will be offset by the benefits obtained from the transmission of information on several learned behaviours.


4. Discussion

 

4.1 Imitator versus only-learner: is imitation adaptive?


The main effect of imitation in the model (a > 0) is to increase the probability that naive individuals learn the variants 1 present in the parental generation. Imitation allows individuals to have access to variants difficult to learn by individual learning, irrespective of the final decision to accept or reject the behaviour. Consequently, the effect of imitation is stronger when the behaviour is more difficult to learn by trial and error learning -low values of h.

In our model, imitation is favoured by natural selection -fitness increases as a increases- whenever the imitated variant 1 has a positive selective value and it is at a disadvantage if the behaviour that can be imitated 1 has a negative fitness value (s < 0). The imitation will be adaptive if the parental behaviours are mostly adaptive. In a more realistic model that considers the possibility of imitating other individuals different from the parents -oblique and horizontal cultural transmission- the probability of knowing any behaviour present in the population will increase and it will approach 1 if the population is small and the number of behaviours is not too great. Therefore, almost all of the individuals will know all the variants present in the parental generation and they will have to decide which of them they accept. In this situation, the crucial aspect for adaptation is the preference of the individuals for the variants with greater fitness or, in other words, a positive correlation between b and fitness.

Our model assumes an asymmetry with respect to the imitation of both variants: variant 1 can be imitated but variant 0 cannot. In some situations this assumption is not realistic because both behaviours can be imitated and can be treated as allele-phenotypes. In these cases, we have shown that imitation is always favoured by natural selection when the parameter a is the same for both phenotypes 1 and 0 (Castro & Toro, 1995).

The model does not distinguish between individuals that really imitate the behaviour they observe -true imitation- and individuals that manage to develop the behaviour by indirect observation -i.e. stimulus enhancement. Both mechanisms raise the probability that individuals will perform and test a behaviour, but do not modify the probability of accepting it. If stimulus enhancement is as efficient as imitation in raising the probability of performing a behaviour, the fitness variation caused by the two mechanisms will be equal.
 

4.2 Only-assessor versus only-learner: is transmission of evaluations adaptive?


The only-assessor individual can approve or disapprove of the behaviour of their offspring. Only-assessor transmits evaluations about behaviours he has learned and categorised previously, in a process of cultural transmission distinct from imitation and that can be called teaching in a strict sense. This transmission can have a cost c that decreases the fitness of only-assessor.

The transmission of the evaluation of behaviour 1 increases or decreases the final probability b* of offspring preferring variant 1 instead of 0, but also increases the phenotypic correlation between parents and offspring. Thus, only-assessor will always be better than only-learner because he increases the frequency of the adaptive behaviour, 1 or 0. Only if the cost c of the transmission of evaluations is great enough, only-assessor can become worse than only-learner. However, the ability to approve or disapprove of offspring’s behaviour is not present in non-human animals. Chimpanzees and other primates do punish behaviour of others but only if this behaviour affects them directly and negatively and this does not require a conceptual categorisation of behaviour. We think that the emergence of this ability required the previous development of the conceptual capacity to categorise learned one's own and others' behaviour as 'positive' or 'negative'.
 

4.3 Assessor: are both imitation and transmission of evaluations together adaptive?


The assessor genotype has both abilities, to imitate and to transmit evaluations. In the model, assessor is the best genotype when the learned behaviour that can be imitated is adaptive (s>0). If behaviour 1 is maladaptive (s<0), genotype assessor can be the worst genotype. The reason is that the imitation of behaviour 1 is maladaptive. However, he can be better than imitator and even better than only-learner if the effect of imitation is small (h close to 1) and the effect of transmission of evaluations is great (d close to 1 and b close to 0). Similar to what happens with only-assessor, if there is a cost c in the transmission of evaluations the fitness of assessor will decrease.

Regardless of how they are acquired -by trial and error, imitation or insight-, behaviours are evaluated by each one of the individuals of the population and accepted or rejected. In our opinion, social learning -stimulus enhancement or true imitation- in primates and other mammals, is not an alternative to individual learning by trial and error -older in the phylogeny- but a complementary mechanism that permits the development of quicker and with higher probability the behaviours present in the parental generation. The assessor parents can generate a more efficient system of cultural inheritance, because they transmit information on both the behaviour and the evaluation of behaviour and, thus, increase the phenotypic correlation between parents and offspring. The cultural transmission that produces assessor is however a flexible inheritance system, because it allows the propagation of innovations. If bis close to 1, a new behaviour that can be imitated through oblique or horizontal transmission will be easily propagated, because parents cannot disapprove of an unknown variant that it is not present in their status. In this way, the efficacy of vertical cultural transmission is compatible with a quick dissemination of innovation through oblique or horizontal transmission.

The existence of biases in the assessment can notably increase the efficiency of assessor. It seems reasonable to admit that individuals can transmit -approve or disapprove of- information on the value of a behaviour with more or less intensity -greater or lower d - depending on the ease or difficulty of the decision process, and on the confidence they have on the decision taken. The biased assessment could occur without any genetic differences among individuals in the value of d . We have put forward the idea that the intellectual capacity of the human species attained its extraordinary development within a framework of social life and cultural transmission of values, as a new structure capable of generating values and showing preferences between different kinds of behaviour (Castro & Toro, 1995; Castro & Toro, 1998; Castro et al., 1998). We think that the cultural transmission of values determined the propagation of memes leading to a process of cultural selection (i.e., the differential survival and reproduction of memes).

The distinction between b and d values helps one understand why an individual can (or cannot) exhibit a behaviour and, at the same time, he can disapprove of (or approve of) this behaviour in other individuals. This property can be useful because it allows the reproof of the imitation of dangerous behaviours before the offspring is prepared to perform them. Moreover, it can produce parental manipulation -i.e. penalising behaviour that serves the offspring's interests, but does not serve the parents'.
 

4.4 Conclusion


Cultural transmission has attained an extraordinary development in our species and is determinant of its own evolution. Human cultural learning created a species-unique process of cumulative cultural evolution. Boyd & Richerson (1996) argue that humans and other primates both engage in the same kinds of social and imitative learning, but there is a quantitative difference in social learning skills that leads to a qualitative difference in the cultural traditions of chimpanzees and humans. On the contrary, Tomasello (1999) suggests that human beings evolved a new form of social cognition, the ability to "identify" with conspecifics, which led to an understanding of them as intentional and mental beings like themselves, which enabled a new process of cumulative cultural evolution. This process depends on innovation, imitative learning, and perhaps active instruction on the part of adults, and cannot be brought about by means of weaker forms of social learning. We maintain that the transition between the chimpanzees' rudimentary cultural transmission -a mixture of stimulus enhancement and true imitation- and the human cultural transmission -based on true imitation and teaching, defined as the transmission of information on the evaluation of the learned behaviour - required the development of the capacity to approve or disapprove of offspring’s behaviour and previously of the conceptual capacity of categorise learned behaviour. Or, in other words, that some of our ancestors became assessor. The approval or disapproval of offspring’s behaviour is a new mode of cultural transmission that increases the accuracy of the process of meme imitation, or in Blackmore (1999) words, the process of 'copy-the-product'. Thus, cultural transmission becomes a system of inheritance and cumulative cultural transmission become possible.

In summary, the success of assessor is due to his capacity to increase the phenotypic correlation between parents and offspring, amplifying the effect of natural selection on learned behaviours -favouring an increase in the adaptive ones and disfavouring the maladaptive ones. Assessor parents can do one important thing that imitators cannot: they can help the offspring to quickly and firmly reject maladaptive behaviour with negative evaluation or adaptive behaviours that are maladaptive at their age. Moreover, assessors can also facilitate the quick propagation of innovations and of the adaptive behaviours when they acquire a positive bias in the cultural transmission of evaluations.


Appendix


Let us consider a population monomorphic for the most complex genotype IA. If f00, f01 and f11 are the phenotypic frequencies in generation t, the values g00, g01 and g11 in generation t+1 will be
 


 

At the equilibrium the frequencies will remain unchanged
 

.

After some algebraic manipulation it can be shown that these equilibrium values will be,
 

The equilibrium frequencies for the less complex genotypes can be easily calculated from the above equations assuming d =(genotype Ia), a =0   (genotype iA) and a =0 ,  b =(genotype ia).

Thus, for the genotypes ia and iA the equilibrium values will be
 

and for the genotype Ia
 


 

Acknowledgements


This work has been developed within the R+D Project: Estudio interdisciplinar de rasgos funcionales del grado humano (BSO2000-116-C04). The work has also been facilitated by concession to L. Castro of a ‘licencia por estudios’ of the local Government of Madrid.


References

Aoki, K., 2001. Theoretical and empirical aspects of gene-culture coevolution. Theoretical Population Biology, 59, 253-261.

Blackmore, S., 1999. The Meme Machine, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J., 1985. Culture and the Evolutionary Process, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.

Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J., 1995. Why does culture increase human adaptability? Ethology and Sociobiology, 16,125-143.

Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J., 1996. Why culture is common but cultural evolution is rare? Proceedings of the British Academy, 88, 77-93.

Byrne, R., & Russon, A. E., 1998. Learning by imitation: A hierarchical approach. Behav. Brain Sci., 21, 667-721.

Castro, L., 1992 .Capacidad ética, transmisión cultural y evolución humana. Arbor, 564, 81-92.

Castro, L., & Toro, M. A., 1995. Human Evolution and the Capacity to Categorise. Journal of Social and Evolutionary Systems, 18, 55-66.

Castro, L., & Toro, M. A., 1998. The long and winding road to the ethical capacity. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 20, 77-92.

Castro, L., Serrano, J.M., & Toro, M. A., 1998. Conceptual capacity to categorize and the evolution of altruism. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 192, 561-565.

Custance, D., Whiten, A., & Fredman, T., 1999. Social learning of an artificial fruit task in capuchin monkeys (Cebus apella). J. Comp. Psychol., 113, 13-23.

Feldman, M. W., & Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., 1984. Cultural and biological evolutionary processes: Gene-culture disequilibrium. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA, 81, 1604-1607.

Feldman, M. W., Aoki, K., & Kumm, J., 1996. Individual versus social learning: Evolutionary analysis in a fluctuating environment. Anthropological Science, 104, 209-232.

Galef, B.G., 1988. Imitation in animals: History, definitions, and interpretations from the psychological laboratory. In Social Learning: Psychological and Biological Approaches. T. Zentall & B.G. Galef (Eds.) Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Assoc.

Galef, B.G., 1992. The question of animal culture. Human Nature, 3, 157-178.

Henrich, J., and Boyd, R., 1998. The evolution of conformist transmission and the emergence of between group-differences. Evolution and Human Behavior, 19, 215-241.

Heyes C.M., & Galef, B.G., JR. (Eds.), 1996. Social Learning in Animals: The Roots of Culture, New York, Academic Press.

Kendal, J. & Laland, K., 2000. Mathematical models for memetics. Journal of Memetics - Evolutionary Models of Information Transmission, 4 (1), http://cfpm.org/jom-emit/2000/vol4/kendal_jr&laland_kn.html.

Maynard Smith, J., & Warren, N. 1982 "Models of cultural and genetic change". Evolution, 36: 620-627.

Rogoff, B., 1990. Apprenticeship in thinking: Cognitive development in social context, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Tomasello, M., 1990. Cultural transmission in the tool use and communicatory signaling of chimpanzees. In "Language" and Intelligence in Monkeys and Apes. Comparative and Developmental Perspectives. S.T. Parker & R.K. Gibson (Eds.) Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Tomasello, M., 1996. Do apes ape? In Social Learning in Animals: The Roots of Culture. C.M. Heyes & B.G. Galef (Eds.) New York: Academic Press.

Tomasello, M., 1999. The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition, Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press.

Tomasello, M., Kruger, A. C., & Ratner, H.H., 1993. Cultural Learning. Behav. Brain Sci., 16, 495-552.

Visalberghi, E., & Fragaszy, D. M., 1990. Do monkeys ape?. In "Language" and Intelligence in Monkeys and Apes. Comparative and Developmental Perspectives. S.T.

Whiten, A., 1998. Imitation of the sequential structure of actions by chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). J. Comp. Psychol., 13, 270-281.

Whiten, A., Goodall, J., McGrew, W.C., Nishida, T., Reynolds, V., Sugiyama, Y., Tutin, C.E.G., Wrangham, R.W., & Boesch, C., 1999. Cultures in chimpanzees. Nature, 399, 682-685.

Whiten, A., & Ham, R., 1992. On the nature and evolution of imitation in the animal kingdom: reappraisal of a century of research. Adv. Study Behav., 21, 239-283.
 

© JoM-EMIT 2002

Back to Issue 2 Volume 6